Last week, we saw that a sentence in a natural
language can be represented in the formal language of logic through predicates,
implications and quantifiers. Yet we can be a little fancier with our representations
by introducing two new members to our zoo of logical symbols.
Suppose that we want to represent these English
statements in logic:
(1) Some student that is in CSC165 is both cool and likes
math.
Let $U$ be the set of all students.
Let $C(x)$ mean $x$ is in CSC165, $K(x)$ mean $x$ is cool
and $M(x)$ mean $x$ likes math. The conjunction symbol, which
represents the English word “and”, and the disjunction symbol, which represents
the word English “or”, allows the translation of statements (1) and (2) into
logic:
(1) $\exists x \in U, C(x)
\implies (K(x) \wedge M(x))$.
(2) $\forall x \in U, C(c)
\implies (K(x) \vee M(x))$.
Now let us play a game of I-Spy. See
these statements:
(3) $\exists x \in U, C(x)
\implies (K(x) \implies M(x))$.
(4)
$\forall x \in U, C(x) \implies (K(x) \implies M(x))$.
I spy a nuance between
statements (3) and (1) and statements (4) and (2). What is this
nuance? It is the relation between predicates $K(x)$ and
$M(x)$. Replacing either the conjunction or disjunction symbol in a statement with
an implication symbol changes the meaning of that statement. Let us
illustrate the difference between statements (1) and (3) and statements (2) and
(4) with a CSC165 student named Bobby.
Bobby wants to take up the burden of satisfying
statement (1). Then he needs be cool and he has to like math. Later
Bobby decides that this is too much of a burden for him so he decides to
satisfy statement (3) instead. From last week`s post about implications,
we know that he has a choice of either being uncool or keeping his fondness for
math. Hence, the implication is much more flexible than the conjunction.
Now Bobby wants to take up the burden of satisfying
statement (2). He campaigns to convince all his CSC165 classmates to
either be cool or like math. His classmates rebel and decide to
neither be cool nor like math. Yet Bobby is enterprising. He
decides to satisfy statement (4) instead. Then he needs to get all his
classmates to either be uncool or like math. However, his CSC165
classmates are just as adept at defying Bobby and they decide to be both cool
and dislike math. Poor Bobby! Hence, the implication and
disjunction are different in how they are satisfied but they are the same in
their flexibility.
No comments:
Post a Comment